514 Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Moral reasons to edit the human genome: picking up from the Nuffield report Christopher Gyngell,1,2 Hilary Bowman-Smart, 2 Julian Savulescu2,3
Feature article
To cite: Gyngell C, Bowman-Smart H, Savulescu J. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523.
1Department of Paediatrics, University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Victoria, Australia 2Murdoch Children’s Research Institute, Melbourne, Victoria, Australia 3Faculty of Philosophy, Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, Oxford, UK
Correspondence to Professor Julian Savulescu, Faculty of Philosophy, The Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, Oxford OX1 1PT, UK; julian. savulescu@ philosophy. ox. ac. uk
Received 7 September 2018 Revised 2 December 2018 Accepted 11 December 2018 Published Online First 24 January 2019
► http:// dx. doi. org/ 10. 1136/ medethics- 2018- 105316
► http:// dx. doi. org/ 10. 1136/ medethics- 2019- 105390
► http:// dx. doi. org/ 10. 1136/ medethics- 2019- 105395
► http:// dx. doi. org/ 10. 1136/ medethics- 2019- 105713
© Author(s) (or their employer(s)) 2019. Re-use permitted under CC BY. Published by BMJ.
AbsTrACT In July 2018, the Nuffield Council of Bioethics released its long-awaited report on heritable genome editing (HGE). The Nuffield report was notable for finding that HGE could be morally permissible, even in cases of human enhancement. In this paper, we summarise the findings of the Nuffield Council report, critically examine the guiding principles they endorse and suggest ways in which the guiding principles could be strengthened. While we support the approach taken by the Nuffield Council, we argue that detailed consideration of the moral implications of genome editing yields much stronger conclusions than they draw. Rather than being merely ’morally permissible’, many instances of genome editing will be moral imperatives.
InTroduCTIon Genome editing technologies have developed rapidly in the last few years, and point to a future where we can precisely edit the human germline. The most powerful gene editing technology is the CRISPR (Clustered Regularly Interspaced Short Palindromic Repeats)-Cas9 system. CRISPR-Cas9 is found naturally in bacteria, where it functions as a defence against viruses by cutting viral DNA into small, non-functional fragments. In 2012, a team at UC Berkeley showed that CRISPR-Cas9 could be modified in the lab, so that it could target virtu- ally any DNA sequence.1 This allows researchers to cut effectively any part of the genome. Further- more, once a DNA strand is broken, the cell’s own repair mechanisms could be recruited to delete, add or modify the sequence. In April 2015, it was announced that CRISPR had been used to make edits in human embryos for the first time.2 In August 2017, researchers in the USA used CRISPR to correct a mutation in human embryos that leads to a fatal heart condition—with virtually no off-target mutations.3 In November 2018, Dr He Jiankui announced that he had used the CRIS- PR-Cas9 system to edit the genomes of twins Lulu and Nana, in an attempt to make them resistant to HIV.4 Although this has not been independently confirmed, if true, it would be the first use of genome editing for human reproduction. This attempt has largely been met with condemnation, including by one of the authors of this paper,5 due to its experimental nature and lack of consideration for the welfare of the children. Such research has generated wide debate about the ethics of genome modification.
Genome editing of germ cells (embryos, sperm and egg cells) was initially very controversial and caused some to call for an outright ban on this application.6 Despite this, there has been a broad
consensus among expert bodies that genome editing in research is morally permissible (see table 1 for summary). However, genome editing for reproduc- tion, a practice called heritable gene editing (HGE), has been much more contentious.
In July 2018, the Nuffield Council on Bioethics released its report ‘Genome editing and human reproduction: social and ethical issues’.7 The report is significant for advocating an approach to the assessment of HGE based on ethical princi- ples rather than applications. Any particular use of HGE could be morally permissible, provided it was consistent with promoting individual welfare and social solidarity.
In this paper, we critically analyse the approach taken by Nuffield report and its conclusions.
In the first section, The Nuffield Council’s report on genome editing and human reproduction, we provide a detailed summary of the Nuffield Coun- cil’s approach. While we applaud the Nuffield Council report as a significant step forward in the debate, we argue there is room to build on and strengthen their approach. In the second section, Social harms and collective action problems, we suggest ways their guiding principles could be improved by removing an implicit asymmetry between the two principles. In the third section, Categorical limits and moral imperatives in HGE, we argue that the conclusions stated in the report do not go far enough. Some uses of HGE are not merely morally permissible but are moral impera- tives, even beyond the treatment of disease. Finally, in the section Governance and public attitudes, we examine the implications of recent attitudinal research by the Pew Centre which shows that the general public may support HGE for treatment but not enhancement.
The nuFFIeld CounCIl’s reporT on genome edITIng And humAn reproduCTIon In 2016, following its report which looked at the ethical issues associated with genome editing more broadly (e.g., including food), the Nuffield Council of Bioethics formed a working group to ‘examine ethical questions relating to the attempted influ- ence of inherited characteristics in humans, in the light of the likely impact of genome editing tech- nologies’. After 2 years of work, the working party released its report titled ‘Genome editing and human reproduction’.
The first two sections of the report contextualise HGE within its immediate potential role as a repro- ductive technology used by individuals, its possible future applications and the social context in which those applications might evolve.
515Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
Ta b
le 1
Re
ce nt
o rg
an is
at io
na l o
r ex
pe rt
b od
y st
at em
en ts
o n
th e
et hi
cs o
f h er
ita bl
e ge
ne e
di tin
g (H
G E)
* Ye
ar b
o d
y Ti
tl e
K ey
p o
in ts
20 18
N uf
fie ld
C ou
nc il
on B
io et
hi cs
G en
om e
ed iti
ng a
nd h
um an
r ep
ro du
ct io
n A
pp lic
at io
ns o
f H G
E m
ay b
e m
or al
ly p
er m
is si
bl e
if th
ey a
re c
on si
st en
t w
ith t
he w
el fa
re o
f t he
fu tu
re p
er so
n an
d so
ci al
ju st
ic e.
T hi
s m
ay a
llo w
fo r
ap pl
ic at
io ns
b ey
on d
pr ev
en tin
g di
se as
e. F
ur th
er r
es ea
rc h
m us
t be
d on
e in
to e
ffi ca
cy a
nd s
af et
y an
d a
br oa
de r
so ci
et al
d eb
at e
m us
t be
fa ci
lit at
ed , a
s w
el l a
s en
su rin
g ad
eq ua
te g
ov er
na nc
e.
20 18
G én
om e
Q ué
be c
& C
en tr
e of
G en
om ic
s an
d Po
lic y
H um
an g
en om
e ed
iti ng
: e th
ic al
a nd
p ol
ic y
co ns
id er
at io
ns Th
e m
od ifi
ca tio
n of
h um
an g
er m
c el
ls a
nd e
m br
yo s
sh ou
ld b
e pe
rm itt
ed in
a b
as ic
o r
pr ec
lin ic
al r
es ea
rc h
co nt
ex t,
an y
fu tu
re c
lin ic
al g
er m
lin e
m od
ifi ca
tio ns
s ho
ul d
be fo
r se
rio us
di
se as
es o
nl y
(a nd
c rit
er ia
n ee
d to
b e
ou tli
ne d)
a nd
a n
in cl
us iv
e ap
pr oa
ch t
o po
lic ym
ak in
g sh
ou ld
b e
en co
ur ag
ed .
20 17
N at
io na
l A ca
de m
y of
S ci
en ce
s, E
ng in
ee rin
g an
d M
ed ic
in e
H um
an g
en om
e ed
iti ng
: s ci
en ce
, e th
ic s
an d
go ve
rn an
ce If
te ch
ni ca
l c ha
lle ng
es r
el at
in g
to s
af et
y an
d ef
fic ac
y w
er e
ov er
co m
e, c
lin ic
al t
ria ls
fo r
H G
E sh
ou ld
o nl
y be
p er
m itt
ed if
t he
re is
a n
ab se
nc e
of r
ea so
na bl
e al
te rn
at iv
es , b
e re
st ric
te d
to
ge ne
s th
at c
le ar
ly c
au se
o r
pr ed
is po
se t
o a
se ve
re d
is ab
ili ty
o r
di se
as e,
w ith
c on
ve rs
io n
on ly
t o
ge ne
s th
at c
ur re
nt ly
e xi
st in
t he
p op
ul at
io n.
R eg
ul at
or y
ov er
si gh
t an
d pu
bl ic
d eb
at e
is
es se
nt ia
l. N
o tr
ia ls
fo r
pu rp
os es
o th
er t
ha n
th e
pr ev
en tio
n of
d is
ea se
s ho
ul d
be p
er m
itt ed
a t
th is
t im
e, b
ut p
ub lic
d eb
at e
on t
he m
at te
r sh
ou ld
b e
fa ci
lit at
ed .
20 17
A m
er ic
an S
oc ie
ty o
f H um
an G
en et
ic s
(A SH
G )†
H um
an g
er m
lin e
ge no
m e
ed iti
ng : A
SH G
p os
iti on
s ta
te m
en t
1.
A t
th is
t im
e, it
is n
ot a
pp ro
pr ia
te t
o co
nd uc
t H
G E
th at
r es
ul ts
in h
um an
p re
gn an
cy .
2.
A s
lo ng
a s
th er
e is
a pp
ro pr
ia te
o ve
rs ig
ht , t
he re
is n
o re
as on
t o
pr oh
ib it
or n
ot u
se p
ub lic
fu nd
s fo
r in
v itr
o ge
rm lin
e ge
ne e
di tin
g fo
r re
se ar
ch in
to c
lin ic
al a
pp lic
at io
ns .
3.
Fu tu
re c
lin ic
al a
pp lic
at io
ns s
ho ul
d on
ly p
ro ce
ed if
t he
re is
: ( i)
a m
ed ic
al r
at io
na le
, ( ii)
s tr
on g
ev id
en ce
b as
e, (i
ii) a
n et
hi ca
l j us
tifi ca
tio n
an d
(iv ) a
t ra
ns pa
re nt
p ub
lic p
ro ce
ss .
20 17
O pi
ni on
G ro
up o
f t he
B io
et hi
cs a
nd L
aw O
bs er
va to
ry , U
ni ve
rs ity
of
B ar
ce lo
na D
ec la
ra tio
n on
b io
et hi
cs a
nd g
en e
ed iti
ng in
h um
an s
A m
or at
or iu
m is
u se
le ss
in a
n in
te rn
at io
na l a
nd c
om pe
tit iv
e sc
ie nt
ifi c
w or
ld . R
eg ul
at or
y fr
am ew
or ks
a re
n ee
de d
to g
ov er
n an
y cl
in ic
al a
pp lic
at io
n of
g er
m lin
e ge
no m
e ed
iti ng
, a nd
it
sh ou
ld n
ot b
e us
ed fo
r en
ha nc
em en
t.
20 17
C ou
nc il
of E
ur op
e Re
co m
m en
da tio
n 21
15 : t
he u
se o
f n ew
g en
et ic
t ec
hn ol
og ie
s in
hu
m an
b ei
ng s
D el
ib er
at e
ge rm
lin e
ed iti
ng in
h um
an b
ei ng
s w
ou ld
c ro
ss a
li ne
v ie
w ed
a s
et hi
ca lly
in vi
ol ab
le . A
r eg
ul at
or y
fr am
ew or
k ne
ed s
to b
e de
ve lo
pe d
an d
a br
oa d
an d
in fo
rm ed
p ub
lic d
eb at
e sh
ou ld
b e
fo st
er ed
.
20 17
Fe de
ra tio
n of
E ur
op ea
n A
ca de
m ie
s of
M ed
ic in
e (F
EA M
) Th
e ap
pl ic
at io
n of
g en
om e
ed iti
ng in
h um
an s
Th er
e ar
e m
aj or
e th
ic al
, s af
et y
an d
ef fic
ac y
is su
es t
ha t
m us
t be
r es
ol ve
d be
fo re
c lin
ic al
a pp
lic at
io ns
o f H
G E
ca n
be c
on si
de re
d. T
he re
is n
o br
oa d
so ci
et al
c on
se ns
us in
E ur
op e.
G
en er
al ly
, F EA
M d
oe s
no t
su pp
or t
ge no
m e
ed iti
ng fo
r no
n- m
ed ic
al in
te rv
en tio
ns (i
nc lu
di ng
s om
at ic
g en
om e
ed iti
ng ),
bu t
an tic
ip at
es a
w id
e- ra
ng in
g pu
bl ic
d is
cu ss
io n
on t
hi s
m at
te r.
20 17
Eu ro
pe an
A ca
de m
ie s
Sc ie
nc e
A dv
is or
y C
ou nc
il G
en om
e ed
iti ng
: s ci
en tifi
c op
po rt
un iti
es , p
ub lic
in te
re st
s an
d po
lic y
op tio
ns in
t he
E ur
op ea
n U
ni on
It w
ou ld
b e
irr es
po ns
ib le
t o
pr oc
ee d
w ith
g er
m lin
e ed
iti ng
u nt
il th
e nu
m er
ou s
sa fe
ty a
nd e
ffi ca
cy c
on ce
rn s
ha ve
b ee
n re
so lv
ed . T
he re
is a
n ee
d fo
r an
o ng
oi ng
fo ru
m .
20 17
A m
er ic
an C
ol le
ge o
f M ed
ic al
G en
et ic
s an
d G
en om
ic s
G en
om e
ed iti
ng in
c lin
ic al
g en
et ic
s: p
oi nt
s to
c on
si de
r Th
er e
ar e
te ch
ni ca
l c on
ce rn
s (e
g, t
he r
is k
of o
ff -t
ar ge
t ef
fe ct
s or
e pi
ge ne
tic e
ff ec
ts t
ha t
m ay
a ff
ec t
m an
y fu
tu re
g en
er at
io ns
) a s
w el
l a s
et hi
ca l c
on ce
rn s
(w hi
ch v
ar ia
nt s
th at
a re
t o
be
ed ite
d ne
ed s
to b
e di
sc us
se d
at a
s oc
ie ta
l l ev
el ).
20 15
N at
io na
l A ca
de m
y of
S ci
en ce
s, E
ng in
ee rin
g an
d M
ed ic
in e
In te
rn at
io na
l s um
m it
on h
um an
g en
e ed
iti ng
It w
ou ld
b e
irr es
po ns
ib le
t o
pr oc
ee d
w ith
a ny
c lin
ic al
u se
o f g
er m
lin e
ed iti
ng u
nl es
s an
d un
til (i
) t he
r el
ev an
t sa
fe ty
a nd
e ffi
ca cy
is su
es h
av e
be en
r es
ol ve
d, b
as ed
o n
ap pr
op ria
te
un de
rs ta
nd in
g an
d ba
la nc
in g
of r
is ks
, p ot
en tia
l b en
efi ts
a nd
a lte
rn at
iv es
, a nd
(i i)
th er
e is
b ro
ad s
oc ie
ta l c
on se
ns us
a bo
ut t
he a
pp ro
pr ia
te ne
ss o
f t he
p ro
po se
d ap
pl ic
at io
n.
20 15
A ca
de m
y of
M ed
ic al
S ci
en ce
s (U
K) ‡
G en
om e
ed iti
ng in
h um
an c
el ls
— in
iti al
jo in
t st
at em
en t
Et hi
ca l a
nd r
eg ul
at or
y qu
es tio
ns m
us t
be d
eb at
ed b
ef or
e cl
in ic
al a
pp lic
at io
ns o
f e di
tin g
ge rm
c el
ls c
an b
e co
ns id
er ed
.
20 15
H in
xt on
G ro
up §
St at
em en
t on
g en
om e
ed iti
ng t
ec hn
ol og
ie s
an d
hu m
an g
er m
lin e
ge ne
tic m
od ifi
ca tio
n W
he n
al l s
af et
y, e
ffi ca
cy a
nd g
ov er
na nc
e ne
ed s
ar e
m et
, t he
re m
ay b
e m
or al
ly a
cc ep
ta bl
e us
es fo
r H
G E
fo r
re pr
od uc
tiv e
pu rp
os es
. F ur
th er
d eb
at e
as t
o w
ha t
sp ec
ifi c
us es
a re
m or
al ly
ac
ce pt
ab le
is r
eq ui
re d.
20 15
A m
er ic
an S
oc ie
ty fo
r G
en e
an d
C el
l T he
ra py
(A SG
C T)
a nd
J ap
an
So ci
et y
of G
en e
Th er
ap y
(J SG
T) A
SG C
T an
d JS
G T
jo in
t po
si tio
n st
at em
en t
on h
um an
g en
om ic
e di
tin g
A s
av ai
la bl
e ge
no m
e ed
iti ng
t ec
hn ol
og ie
s ar
e in
ad eq
ua te
ly u
nd er
st oo
d, a
nd b
ec au
se t
he r
es ul
ts o
f s uc
h m
an ip
ul at
io n
co ul
d no
t be
u nd
er st
oo d
fo r
de ca
de s
or g
en er
at io
ns , t
he se
s af
et y
an d
ef fic
ac y
co nc
er ns
a re
s uf
fic ie
nt ly
s er
io us
t o
su pp
or t
a st
ro ng
s ta
nc e
ag ai
ns t
H G
E.
20 15
A lli
an ce
fo r
Re ge
ne ra
tiv e
M ed
ic in
e¶ D
o no
t ed
it th
e hu
m an
g er
m lin
e Th
e sc
ie nt
ifi c
co m
m un
ity is
u rg
ed t
o en
ga ge
in d
ia lo
gu e
an d
pu t
in p
la ce
a v
ol un
ta ry
m or
at or
iu m
t o
di sc
ou ra
ge h
um an
g er
m lin
e m
od ifi
ca tio
n. T
hi s
is d
ue t
o sc
ie nt
ifi c
an d
et hi
ca l r
is ks
su
ch a
s th
at p
er m
itt in
g ev
en u
na m
bi gu
ou sl
y th
er ap
eu tic
in te
rv en
tio ns
c ou
ld s
ta rt
d ow
n a
pa th
t ow
ar ds
n on
-t he
ra pe
ut ic
g en
et ic
e nh
an ce
m en
t.
20 15
IG I F
or um
o n
Bi oe
th ic
s, N
ap a,
C al
ifo rn
ia **
A p
ru de
nt p
at h
fo rw
ar d
fo r
ge no
m ic
e ng
in ee
rin g
an d
ge rm
lin e
ge ne
m
od ifi
ca tio
n 1.
A
ny a
tt em
pt s
at c
lin ic
al a
pp lic
at io
ns o
f g er
m lin
e ge
ne e
di tin
g ar
e st
ro ng
ly d
is co
ur ag
ed .
2.
Ex pe
rt fo
ru m
s of
s ci
en tis
ts a
nd b
io et
hi ci
st s
m us
t be
h el
d to
fu rt
he r
di sc
us s
th es
e is
su es
. 3.
Tr
an sp
ar en
t re
se ar
ch s
ho ul
d be
e nc
ou ra
ge d
an d
su pp
or te
d. 4.
A
g lo
ba lly
r ep
re se
nt at
iv e
gr ou
p of
a w
id e
ra ng
e of
s ta
ke ho
ld er
s (in
cl ud
in g
th e
ge ne
ra l p
ub lic
a nd
g ov
er nm
en t
bo di
es ) s
ho ul
d be
a ss
em bl
ed t
o fu
rt he
r di
sc us
s th
es e
is su
es a
nd
m ak
e po
lic y
re co
m m
en da
tio ns
.
20 15
In te
rn at
io na
l S oc
ie ty
fo r
St em
C el
l R es
ea rc
h (IS
SC R)
†† Th
e IS
SC R
st at
em en
t on
h um
an g
er m
lin e
ge no
m e
m od
ifi ca
tio n
A ny
c on
si de
ra tio
n of
a pp
ly in
g nu
cl ea
r ge
no m
e ed
iti ng
t o
th e
hu m
an g
er m
lin e
in c
lin ic
al p
ra ct
ic e
ra is
es s
ig ni
fic an
t et
hi ca
l, so
ci et
al a
nd s
af et
y co
ns id
er at
io ns
. T he
re fo
re , t
he IS
SC R
ca lls
fo
r a
m or
at or
iu m
o n
ge rm
lin e
ge no
m e
ed iti
ng in
c lin
ic al
p ra
ct ic
e (e
xc ep
tin g
m ito
ch on
dr ia
l r ep
la ce
m en
t th
er ap
y) , a
lth ou
gh in
v itr
o re
se ar
ch is
s up
po rt
ed .
20 15
N at
io na
l I ns
tit ut
es o
f H ea
lth (N
IH )
St at
em en
t on
N IH
fu nd
in g
of r
es ea
rc h
us in
g ge
ne -e
di tin
g te
ch no
lo gi
es in
h um
an e
m br
yo s
Sa fe
ty , e
th ic
al a
nd r
eg ul
at or
y is
su es
m ea
ns t
ha t
al te
rin g
th e
hu m
an g
er m
lin e
in e
m br
yo s
is ‘a
li ne
t ha
t sh
ou ld
n ot
b e
cr os
se d’
. N IH
w ill
n ot
fu nd
a ny
u se
o f g
en e
ed iti
ng in
e m
br yo
s. (N
.B .:
as o
f 2 01
8, N
IH is
fu nd
in g
re se
ar ch
in to
s om
at ic
c el
l g en
om e
ed iti
ng ).
*O rg
an is
at io
na l r
ec om
m en
da tio
ns a
re in
cl ud
ed h
er e.
A s
ea rc
h w
as c
on du
ct ed
u si
ng a
b ra
nc he
d st
ra te
gy , b
eg in
ni ng
w ith
t he
u se
o f s
ea rc
h te
rm s
in d
at ab
as es
s uc
h as
P ub
M ed
a nd
G oo
gl e
Sc ho
la r
us in
g se
ar ch
t er
m s
su ch
a s
‘h um
an h
er ita
bl e
ge no
m e
ed iti
ng ’,
‘g er
m lin
e ge
ne e
di tin
g’ , ‘
ge no
m e
ed iti
ng e
m br
yo s’
, ‘ ge
rm lin
e en
gi ne
er in
g’ , ‘
hu m
an g
er m
lin e
ed iti
ng ’+
‘e th
ic s’
, ‘ po
lic y’
a nd
/o r
‘r ec
om m
en da
tio ns
’. Fu
rt he
rm or
e, c
ita tio
ns a
nd r
ef er
en ce
s w
er e
ex am
in ed
t o
ge ne
ra te
fu rt
he r
re su
lts . A
la rg
e nu
m be
r of
p ap
er s
w er
e id
en tifi
ed d
is cu
ss in
g th
es e
is su
es , i
nc lu
di ng
a n
um be
r of
r ec
om m
en da
tio ns
. R es
ul ts
w er
e lim
ite d
to t
ho se
fr om
2 00
8 on
w ar
ds (i
e, t
he p
as t
de ca
de a
t tim
e of
w rit
in g)
; a ll
pa pe
rs b
y in
di vi
du al
s or
g ro
up s
of in
di vi
du al
s no
t re
pr es
en tin
g an
o rg
an is
at io
n, b
od y
or
co nf
er en
ce w
er e
di sc
ar de
d, a
s w
el l a
s em
pi ric
al r
es ea
rc h
in to
o pi
ni on
s on
g er
m lin
e ed
iti ng
b y
sp ec
ifi c
se ct
or s
of s
oc ie
ty (e
g, g
en er
al p
ub lic
, h ea
lth ca
re p
ro fe
ss io
na ls
). Th
e fin
al g
ro up
o f r
es ul
ts w
as li
m ite
d to
o rg
an is
at io
ns w
ho se
r em
it in
cl ud
es h
um an
g en
et ic
s, g
en et
ic s
po lic
y, b
io et
hi cs
, r ep
ro du
ct iv
e te
ch no
lo gi
es a
nd /o
r em
er gi
ng t
ec hn
ol og
ie s.
O rg
an is
at io
na l r
es po
ns es
t o
st at
em en
ts a
nd
jo ur
na l e
di to
ria ls
w er
e no
t in
cl ud
ed . T
hi s
lis t
is n
ot e
xh au
st iv
e. †S
ta te
m en
t en
do rs
ed b
y U
K A
ss oc
ia tio
n of
G en
et ic
N ur
se s
an d
C ou
ns el
lo rs
, C an
ad ia
n A
ss oc
ia tio
n of
G en
et ic
C ou
ns el
lo rs
, I nt
er na
tio na
l G en
et ic
E pi
de m
io lo
gy S
oc ie
ty , U
S N
at io
na l S
oc ie
ty o
f G en
et ic
C ou
ns el
or s,
A m
er ic
an S
oc ie
ty fo
r Re
pr od
uc tiv
e M
ed ic
in e,
A si
a Pa
ci fic
S oc
ie ty
o f H
um an
G en
et ic
s, B
rit is
h So
ci et
y fo
r G
en et
ic M
ed ic
in e,
H um
an G
en et
ic s
So ci
et y
of A
us tr
al as
ia , P
ro fe
ss io
na l
So ci
et y
of G
en et
ic C
ou ns
el or
s in
A si
a, a
nd S
ou th
er n
A fr
ic an
S oc
ie ty
fo r
H um
an G
en et
ic s.
T he
A lli
an ce
fo r
Re ge
ne ra
tiv e
M ed
ic in
e (a
n in
te rn
at io
na l m
ul tis
ta ke
ho ld
er g
ro up
, i nc
lu di
ng c
om m
er ci
al s
ta ke
ho ld
er s)
, r el
ea se
d a
st at
em en
t su
pp or
tin g
th is
p os
iti on
. ‡J
oi nt
s ta
te m
en t
w ith
t he
A ss
oc ia
tio n
of M
ed ic
al R
es ea
rc h
C ha
rit ie
s, t
he M
ed ic
al R
es ea
rc h
C ou
nc il
an d
th e
W el
lc om
e Tr
us t.
§A g
ro up
c on
si st
in g
of a
n in
te rn
at io
na l c
ol le
ct io
n of
a ca
de m
ic s
fr om
d is
ci pl
in es
s uc
h as
t he
li fe
s ci
en ce
s, p
hi lo
so ph
y, m
ed ic
in e
an d
ec on
om ic
s, fr
om u
ni ve
rs iti
es in
cl ud
in g
Jo hn
H op
ki ns
, O xf
or d
an d
Lo nd
on S
ch oo
l o f E
co no
m ic
s. ¶
A g
ro up
c on
si st
in g
of c
om m
er ci
al c
om pa
ni es
, r es
ea rc
h in
st itu
tio ns
, n on
-p ro
fit o
rg an
is at
io ns
a nd
p at
ie nt
a dv
oc ac
y gr
ou ps
. C or
po ra
tio ns
c om
pr is
e 73
% o
f s ta
ke ho
ld er
s an
d th
us t
hi s
or ga
ni sa
tio n
sh ou
ld b
e pr
im ar
ily c
on si
de re
d to
r ep
re se
nt t
he v
ie w
s of
c or
po ra
tio ns
s uc
h BD
B io
sc ie
nc es
, G E
H ea
lth ca
re , G
SK , M
ill ip
or eS
ig m
a, N
ov ar
tis a
nd P
fiz er
, a m
on g
m an
y ot
he rs
. T he
y la
te r
re le
as ed
a
st at
em en
t su
pp or
tin g
th e
A SH
G p
os iti
on s
ta te
m en
t (s
ee fo
ot no
te 1
). **
A la
rg e
nu m
be r
of e
xp er
t st
ak eh
ol de
rs a
tt en
de d
an d
m ad
e th
is p
os iti
on s
ta te
m en
t, in
cl ud
in g
th e
in ve
nt or
s of
C RI
SP R-
C as
9. ††
A n
on -p
ro fit
o rg
an is
at io
n en
co ur
ag in
g re
se ar
ch in
to t
he u
se o
f s te
m c
el ls
.
516 Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
The report states that genome editing in the context of repro- duction must be situated against a background of increased genetic knowledge informing reproductive options. Increased knowledge about genetic differences has created an ‘epistemic shift’ revealing previous dichotomies between states of health and disease, and thus therapeutic and non-therapeutic applica- tions, to be inadequate (p. 26). Even if one views HGE as only permissible within the context of ‘therapeutic’ applications, its position as a reproductive technology means that it cannot be viewed as straightforwardly therapeutic in the same way as other medical technologies. HGE is not therapeutic in the sense that nobody who is in a current state of disease is being treated, but nor is it straightforwardly preventative (because the risk could be addressed by not having children) (pp. 22–23). Genomic inter- vention in reproduction is distinct from other human applica- tions because it deals with possible persons rather than existing persons; it must be viewed as a means of fulfilling reproductive desires rather than a means of preventing disease (p. 47, foot- note 143).
The report goes on to say that genetic information (that can be acquired by a number of technologies) places new responsi- bilities on whether to act or not act on this information when considering reproduction. Prospective parents who wish to use this knowledge to avoid or ensure certain genetic variants in their offspring are seeking specific outcomes. They desire a specific kind of child, that is, one that is genetically related to them and does/does not have a specific trait, condition or char- acteristic (p. 23). Existing assisted reproductive technologies, such as pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, provide one way for parents to pursue such goals, but rely on a sufficient abundance of embryos. If this is not possible, HGE may be more accept- able than other means to achieve parenthood such as donated gametes, due to the strong preference many people have for genetically related offspring (p. 25).
The report next situates the development of genome editing within its technical possibilities and a social and political context. Here, the report highlights that genome editing should not be viewed in isolation as an ‘innovation’, but instead encour- ages us to consider what a society in which it is widely available might look like. It outlines various strategies by which HGE might be deployed, including at the zygote stage on embryos created through in vitro fertilisation (IVF), and the possibility of creating modified gametes from induced pluripotent stem (iPS) cells instead of editing embryos directly (pp. 37–39).
There are a number of situations identified in the report where HGE may be the only option to create a genetically related child. These include the cases of Y-chromosome defects, or dominant conditions where one parent is homozygous (p. 45). More likely scenarios where HGE may be necessary are those where the chance of an unaffected embryo would be low to very low. For example, one or both parents may be heterozygous for a dominant condition, or cases where there are multiple undesired independently sorting variants (p. 45). Although not mentioned in the report, another circumstance where HGE might be the only option to create healthy genetically related children is when dominant de novo mutations occur in the germ cell line, such as within spermatogonial stem cells.
The report even raises the possibility of using HGE to avoid complex conditions that are common in populations and are difficult to avoid through selective approaches, because of the large numbers of genes involved (p. 46). Looking forward to a future in which HGE is widely available, the report envisages a wide range of possible applications. These include increased immunity and resistance to disease, tolerance for adverse
environmental conditions (such as that of space), superabilities or other various factors such as the ability to make vitamins rather than having to consume them (p. 47).
The report notes that the social and political drivers for the development of this technology may initially be the use of embryos for ‘basic’ research. However, researchers cannot be morally insulated from the ethical implications of further uses that might develop from applied research (pp. 48–49). The report supports responsible research and innovation, encour- aging reflection that may counteract technological momentum (p. 49). The use of genome editing in human reproduction has the potential to be socially transformative, and policy and regu- lation will play a key role in how this transformation may play out. The report identifies three kinds of concerns about the inte- gration of new technologies into the landscape: first, that we may simply ‘sleepwalk’ into a new world, due to uncontrolled technological momentum; second, that the technology may be subject to function creep, where its use expands in possibly morally troubling ways; and third, that we may be headed down a slippery slope with no reliable ethical or legal means to distin- guish morally unacceptable applications from morally acceptable ones (p. 55). Identifying these concerns can help to recognise key points in the process where better governance and ethical reflection may play an even more important role.
The report’s approach to the ethical issues surrounding HGE is largely framed around the concept of human rights and inter- ests, with a view to the production of general principles. It exam- ines the ethical issues through the lens of three different kinds of interests: (i) individuals directly affected by the technology (the parents and the future person), (ii) society, particularly those who may collaterally affected in less immediate and direct ways (such as people with genetic conditions) and (iii) the interests of humanity in general and future generations (p. 59). This exam- ination concludes that ‘none of the considerations raised yields an ethical principle that would constitute a categorical reason to prohibit heritable genome editing interventions’ (p. xviii).
The report observes that, in terms of the interests of individ- uals, the use of HGE must be balanced between the prospective parents’ interests and the welfare of the future person that may result. Prospective parents often desire a child that is geneti- cally related to them, for a variety of reasons, most of which are ‘felt as well as reasoned’ (p. 59). Nonetheless, it does not necessarily follow that these desires constitute any sort of moral claim to a genetically related child. However, the report looks at two reasons why individuals should be supported in their repro- ductive projects. The first is from the view that procreation is a good, with a naturalist perspective seeing it as an essential part of human function and flourishing or the satisfaction of a natural human desire. More moderately, a view of procreation as a good can come from a recognition that social arrangements favour procreation. However, as the report concludes, it is distinctly difficult to position procreation as a good in itself (pp. 62–63). The second reason people should be supported in their repro- ductive projects stems from a respect for procreative interests. These interests lead to both a negative right and a positive right, although the extent to which the latter is applicable is likely to be dependent on social context (pp. 63–64).
The reproductive interests of the parents must, however, be constrained by another set of interests: that of the future person. This, of course, raises issues such as the non-identity problem, which the report addresses in the following fashion. There are a number of possible children that exist in the form of mental images that the parents may have; as more and more decisions are made during the reproduction process, the diversity of these
517Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
possible children narrows to become closer to the nature of the actual future child. These decisions can be about various proper- ties of the child, and such properties can include those relating to the child’s levels of welfare. The parents bear responsibility for the state of affairs that result from their decisions, which carry moral weight (pp. 66–67). The report examines the extent and limits of this responsibility. It discusses arguments that have been put forward that (i) no genome editing is permissible (such as those autonomy-based arguments from Habermas), (ii) some genome editing is permissible (generally drawing a distinction between ‘therapeutic’ and ‘enhancement’ applications) and (iii) some genome editing is morally required (similar to the principle of procreative beneficence).
The report addresses a number of issues with all of these approaches. The first set of arguments raise the issue of genetic determinism, and the question of how genome editing can be sufficiently demarcated from other parenting strategies in a way that is morally coherent (p. 68). The second falls prey to the difficulty of distinguishing therapeutic applications from enhancement, including but not limited to disability rights and feminist critiques of the normativity implicit in any such argu- ment (pp. 69–72). About the third, the report raises concerns about the application of this principle in practice, such as the ability to sufficiently and reliably identify genomic variants asso- ciated with welfare, and the risk of the burden of expectation (p. 72). However, all these approaches inform the first principle that the report formulates: the use of genome editing technolo- gies must secure and be consistent with the welfare of any future person that may be born as a result of those technologies (p. 75). This principle is necessary but not sufficient for any application of HGE to be morally permissible.
principle 1: the welfare of the future person Gametes or embryos that have been subject to genome editing procedures (or that are derived from cells that have been subject to such procedures) should be used only where the procedure is carried out in a manner and for a purpose that is intended to secure the welfare of and is consistent with the welfare of a person who may be born as a consequence of treatment using those cells.
It is notable that in the formulation of this principle, the Nuffield Council has specifically referenced a general approach focused on the welfare of the future person rather than any particular distinction between different applications of HGE, such as ‘ther- apeutic’ versus ‘enhancement’. As the report itself notes, it is very difficult to draw a clear distinction between therapeutic and non-therapeutic applications and this approach sidesteps this difficulty. The report explicitly states that there is no a priori reason that applications beyond the prevention of disease would not also be consistent with the welfare of the future person (p. 76). This is a significant step in opening the door for a variety of traits and characteristics to be considered for HGE. For example, this raises the possibility of actively including certain welfare-im- proving characteristics, rather than limiting HGE to the removal of welfare-diminishing characteristics.
The report goes on to address the interests of society, noting that reproduction takes place in a social context. Reproductive behaviours already can change the composition of a society without deliberate coordination, but reproductive technologies allow for this with greater certainty (p. 78). Other people in society may be collaterally and indirectly affected by the use of HGE. The report highlights questions surrounding diversity, shifting norms, disability critiques, social virtues and equity and justice.
The report notes that it is possible that genome editing could lead to changes in the level of diversity within the population— whether more or less would depend strongly on prevailing social factors (pp. 79–80). If the use of HGE becomes standard, this could lead to a shift in norms and the expectation of its use, which could decrease freedom. This can be reflected in current concerns around prenatal screening—what people typically do becomes what people should do, and thus what people feel pres- sured to do (pp. 80–82). This follows on to disability critiques, such as the expressivist objection, which states that attempts to deselect or prevent disability expresses or presupposes a negative view of people with a disability. However, the Nuffield Council explicitly rejects this objection when it comes to genetic condi- tions that significantly affect both quality and length of life (p. 82). Another set of critiques is that HGE represents attempts to overcome fragility and weakness, which are in themselves a valu- able part of the human condition and should not be removed. However, the difficulty with these approaches is that a person would have to value such fragility enough that they would be willing to impart it on their own children (pp. 82–85). Finally, the report considers the importance of equity and justice and concludes that HGE should be restricted so as not to result in unfair advantages for certain groups of people (pp. 85–86). This leads on to the second principle formulated in the report (p. 87).
principle 2: social justice and solidarity The use of gametes or embryos that have been subject to genome editing procedures (or that are derived from cells that have been subject to such procedures) should be permitted only in circumstances in which it cannot reasonably be expected to produce or exacerbate social division or the unmitigated marginalisation or disadvantage of groups within society.
The third set of interests that the report addresses is that of humanity and future generations. Potential adverse effects of HGE may only manifest themselves after several generations, and here the notion that we have responsibilities or moral obligations to future generations is key (p. 89). One perspec- tive is that HGE could offer a means to remedy harms that have already been set in motion for future generations, such as runaway climate change (pp. 89–90). However, invoking the ‘precautionary principle’ would suggest that the uncertainty and possible negative consequences of HGE mean that it should not be applied. However, as the report notes, this constitutes no reason not to continue research and the development of the technology as a means of hedging bets against future events (pp. 90–91).
The report also addresses the relationship between HGE and transhumanism. Transhumanism is a concept that is closely linked to the emergence of technologies such as HGE. HGE could lead to the ‘self-overcoming’ of the human species to a grander, more capable species, and the report questions whether this constitutes a moral reason not to apply it. This may stem from a notion of a fundamental human dignity. HGE might be troubling because it threatens the integrity of human genetic inheritance (interference with the line of transmission that links the human family together) and the integrity of human genomic identity (distinguishing the human family from non-human beings) (p. 91). These concerns could be mitigated by replacing variants only with wild-type or typical variants, but of course the question of what is a wild-type or mutant variant is often value-laden in itself. The human genome is enormously varied, and many new variants are possible and likely to emerge. The report responds to this by stating that concerns about moving
518 Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
the human genome away from wild-type variants are pruden- tial, rather than a categorical moral reason not to do so (p. 92). However, questions remain surrounding justice and equity, and the possibility of schisms between the ‘gene-rich’ and the ‘gene- poor’ (pp. 92–95).
The report concludes by stating that there are no categorical limits on the use of genome editing technologies, as long as (p. 97):
► They are not biologically reckless; ► They are consistent with the welfare of future people; ► They are not socially divisive; ► They are not initiated without prior societal debate. We applaud the Nuffield Council’s approach to HGE and
think it is an important step forward in the debate. A strength of the approach is that it outlines quite specific moral principles rather than merely appealing to broad concepts—such as earlier reports.
For example, the National Academiy of Sciences (NAS) report on genome editing endorses the principle of:
Promoting well-being: the principle of promoting well-being supports providing benefit and preventing harm to those affected, often referred to in the bioethics literature as the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence.
It is left unspecified whose well-being we should be promoting through genome editing, what the components of well-being/harm are and exactly how that principle should apply to genome editing. Nearly all people would freely endorse this principle (and many of the other principles relied on in the National Academy of sciences report), but might draw radically different conclusions regarding genome editing. In contrast, the Nuffield Council’s first principle is much more specific and the scope and force is clear.
Nonetheless, there is room to improve and build from the Nuffield Council’s approach. In the next section, we show how an asymmetry in the structure between the two guiding princi- ples leads to counterintuitive implications for an important set of possible uses for HGE, and suggest ways their second prin- ciple could be improved.
soCIAl hArms And ColleCTIve ACTIon problems The first guiding principle adopted by the Nuffield Council concerns its effect on individuals. The report draws on the term ‘welfare’, which is explained as ‘a broader concept than well-being (“being well”, ie, “healthy”). In this sense, psychoso- cial welfare, and not just good health, is an important consid- eration’ (p. 76). Genome editing is only morally permissible if it is ‘carried out in a manner and for a purpose that is intended to secure the welfare of and is consistent with the welfare of a person who may be born’ (p. 75).
A relatively broad range of ways in which individuals could be harmed or wronged is discussed in the report. This includes the effects of genome editing on one’s physical health, and people’s psychological well-being, including any state ‘that might give the future person reasonable grounds to reprove their parents’ (p. 96).
In contrast, principle 2—which looks at the social effects of genome editing—is quite specific. Genome editing would be impermissible if it were ‘to produce or exacerbate social division or the unmitigated marginalisation or disadvantage of groups’ (p. 87). But this principle seems to overlook the fact that there are many ways in which society could be made worse that do not involve the creation of social division or marginalisation. If everyone in society were to be made significantly worse off,
but in a way that did not increase inequality (or even possibly decreased it), we would still most likely view this as an undesir- able state of affairs.
One strand of arguments in the literature on genetic enhance- ment centre on so-called ‘collective action problems’.8–10 In a collective action problem, one option is optimific from the perspective of an individual but results in collective harms if everyone pursues it. Imagine if it becomes possible to use HGE select for or against the predisposition to particular personality traits, such as extroversion. Extroversion is highly heritable11 and associated with increased levels of subjective well-being.12 Furthermore, recent studies have shown that mothers value extroversion in their children above other traits such as intelli- gence and conscientiousness.13 It is therefore plausible that were parents able to access HGE to increase their chances of having an extroverted child, they would use it. This would be consis- tent with both of the Nuffield Council’s guiding principles. As extroversion is associated with higher levels of subjective well- being, such a change would be consistent with the welfare of the child. While decreasing the frequency of introverts in society might lead to increased division and marginalisation as they become ‘the odd one out’, this is not necessarily so (they might become more highly prized as they become rarer). At any rate, the wrongness of such selection should not depend entirely on the contingent response of individuals to the decreasing features of a trait such as introversion.
If HGE were to dramatically increase the rate of extroverts in society, there is a sense that this would make society imperson- ally worse. Introverts contribute important forms of cognitive diversity which can benefit group problem solving.14 15 Having introverts in society can thus benefit many areas of life including achievement in the science and the arts.16
The ability of parents to target other characteristics through HGE, including height and innate immunity, could also lead to collective action problems.8 Such edits would be consistent with welfare of the child, yet if many people made those changes to their children, it could make society worse off in ways that do not necessarily involve increasing social division or marginalisa- tion. If the average height of the population increased, this could increase the amount of resources that we use, and thus damage the environment. If many people selected similar immune genes for their children, this could leave us more susceptible to novel pathogens in the future.
This is not a criticism of the Nuffield Council’s report, as the type of HGE applications which could lead to collective problems are a long way off—and their consideration is not a pressing concern for the regulation of HGE now. However, reflection on them suggests ways in which the Nuffield report’s guiding principles could be improved. Namely, the second prin- ciple should evoke a broader concept of social harm, analogous to the concept of welfare in the first principle.
modified principle 2: social harms The use of gametes or embryos that have been subject to genome editing procedures (or that are derived from cells that have been subject to such procedures) should be permitted only in circumstances in which it cannot reasonably be expected to produce or exacerbate social harms, including increased social division or the unmitigated marginalisation or disadvantage of groups within society.
While this principle loses some of the advantageous of spec- ificity, it has the resources to respond to concerns relating to collective action problems.
519Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
CATegorICAl lImITs And morAl ImperATIves In hge As stated above, the central conclusion of the Nuffield report on HGE was that there are no categorical limits on its use, provided applications are consistent with its guiding principles and preceded with broad public debate. We believe much stronger conclusions regarding the ethics of HGE can be drawn.
Technologies like HGE cannot be good or bad absolutely. We can speak of whether a particular application of a technology is good or bad, or whether their availability has good or bad effects on society—but technologies themselves are not the type of object to which the property of ‘good’ or ‘bad’ attaches.
The most basic ethical questions regarding HGE is therefore whether particular applications of it are good, bad, permissible, desirable, etc. In this section, we will examine some possible applications of HGE and show that rather than being merely morally permissible, some applications will be moral imperatives.
single gene disorders A mark of success of medical genetics has been the diagnosis of the disease phenylketonuria (PKU) at birth. This is an inher- ited metabolic disorder in which levels of the enzyme phenylal- anine hydroxylase are lowered. This means individuals cannot metabolise the amino acid phenylalanine. In 1962, a test was devised that allowed PKU to be diagnosed through a blood test.17 The ‘heel prick test’ is now routinely given to infants as part of newborn screening. Those children who are identified as suffering from PKU are put on a low phenylalanine diet or else they will develop severe intellectual disability. This diet means no bread, pasta, soybeans, egg whites, meat, legumes, nuts, watercress and fish. Such an environmental intervention is demanding. There is always a risk that foods containing phenyl- alanine will be consumed by mistake. The ubiquitous sweetener, aspartame, can cause a crisis.
Imagine an artificial enzyme was developed to replace phenyl- alanine. If this was administered regularly it would allow sufferers of PKU to consume a normal diet. Such a cure would be hailed as a breakthrough. There would be a moral imperative to provide this cure, just as there is an imperative to provide blood transfusion for severe bleeding, and antibiotics for infection.
Now imagine that instead of getting a pharmaceutical company to manufacture the enzyme, we could get the body to manufacture it. By altering the DNA of someone with PKU, we could get a patient’s own cells to produce the missing enzyme, phenylalanine hydroxylase. There are many advantages to not relying on pharmaceutical companies. Production inside the body allows for a more targeted response and more accurate dosages. Furthermore, it removes all chance that a patient would be unable to access the treatment, such as when the company has supply chain problems.i
Just as there would be a moral imperative to provide a replace- ment enzyme therapy for PKU, there would be an imperative to make safe genome edits which prevent PKU. If it becomes possible for carriers of the PKU mutation to prevent PKU in their
i It should be noted that the parents of the affected child will need to access HGE again if they want to ensure any future children they have are also unaffected. Given the cost associated with HGE, this may be seen as creating a division between parents who can and cannot afford it. However, such issues of access already exist for parents of children with PKU, which can cost around US$10 000 per year for the medical food and formula. HGE will certainly be much cheaper than the cost of treating PKU over a lifetime—it could thus help reduce such inequities. For a more complete discussions, see Gyngell et al.43 We thank an anonymous reviewer for making us confront this issue.
future children through HGE, they will have an obligation to use this technology, in the same way they would have an obligation to use an enzyme replacement therapy.
Preimplantation genetic testing and HGE The Nuffield report notes that in all but ‘extremely rare’ (p.44) cases, monogenic diseases like PKU can already be prevented through IVF in combination with preimplantation genetic testing (PGT), with the proviso that ‘it might not be reasonable to expect sufficient viable embryos with the characteristics sought to be available’ (p. 46). Let us try to put some numbers around the cases in which HGE would provide benefits over PGT in preventing single gene disorders due to a lack of viable embryos. In 2013 (the last year for which data are available), 18% of IVF cycles conducted in the UK produced only one viable embryo.18 So, for every 100 couples who go through IVF with the intention of using PGT to avoid disease, approximately 18 will produce a single viable embryo. In 2016 (the last year for which there is data), there were roughly 700 cycles of PGT for genetic disease in the UK.19 So, every year in the UK, around 126 IVF cycles are conducted for PGT and only produce one viable embryo. In these cases, it will not be possible to use genetic selection to avoid diseases. As people choose to attempt to conceive children later and later in life, in part for educational and career reasons, there will be a greater and greater scarcity of embryos.
The most common scenario in which couples use PGT is when they are both are carriers for recessive conditions. In these cases, there is a 25% chance that an embryo will carry both copies of the disease-predisposing mutation. This would imply that there are 31 cases in the UK per year in which HGE could avoid genetic disease in an embryo which PGT cannot. However, this is likely a conservative estimate. When parents are homozygous for dominant conditions like Huntington’s disease, or cases where there are multiple undesirable independently sorting variants, the number of affected embryos will be closer to 50%. One IVF company is on record as estimate that 48% of embryos which undergo PGT are affected by a genetic condition,20 although this will vary clinic to clinic.
Extrapolating from the above numbers would imply that, worldwide, there are several hundred cases a year where HGE would be the only option to produce unaffected offspring.
While several hundred cases a year can be considered rare, it is not negligible. If a public health measure could reduce the incidence of serious disease by several hundred a year, then we would have strong reasons to implement it. It would not merely be ‘morally permissible’ to take such a measure, but something that we actively ought to do. Of course, in situations of limited resources we have reasons to prefer interventions that maximise benefit, but this does not negate the moral reasons we have to benefit the few.
In sum, the application of HGE to prevent of single gene disorders is a good application of technology, and something we have moral reasons to pursue. If it were possible to use HGE to prevent single gene disorders, there would be a moral imperative to use it for this purpose. Of course, given this application alone may not benefit a large number of people, it may not justify using limited health resources developing HGE which could be spent on more effective health measures. But HGE also has potential to prevent far more common causes of disease, as we will explain in the next section.
polygenic diseases Most diseases are not the result of just a few genetic changes. They are the result of many, sometimes hundreds, of genes combining
520 Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
together with environmental effects. Such polygenic diseases are among the world’s biggest killers. Cardiovascular disease is emerging as the biggest cause of death in the low-income and middle-income world. Together deaths from chronic diseases in those under 70 years are responsible for approximately 30% of all deaths worldwide.21 In addition to causing pain and death to individuals, chronic diseases place a huge burden on national health systems, consuming resources that could be used else- where. One study found that the healthcare cost associated with treating cardiovascular disease totalled €104 billion annually, for countries within the European Union.22
We know that there are genetic contributions to chronic diseases. Genome-wide association studies have identified at least 44 genes involved in diabetes23; 35 genes involved in coro- nary artery disease24 and over 300 genes involved in common cancers.25
It is possible to differentiate between individuals based on their genetic risk of developing chronic diseases. Using next-gen- eration sequencing technologies (like whole genome or whole exome sequencing), polymorphisms occurring across many genes can be tallied and weighted giving an individual a ‘poly- genic risk score’ that reflects their genetic predispositions to develop particular diseases and traits. Individuals can then be stratified into different risk categories (such as high risk, medium risk and low risk) based on their polygenic risk score.26
As genome editing technologies can target many genes at one time, it may become possible to use them to alter an individual’s polygenic risk score at the embryonic stage,ii and shift individ- uals from a high-risk category to a low-risk category.iiiiv
Alternatively, it will be possible for individuals who know they have a high polygenic risk to particular diseases to use HGE to alter their gametes to ensure they do not pass this high risk on to their children.
For example, by editing around 27 mutations associated with coronary heart disease, it would be possible to reduce an individ- ual’s lifetime risk by 42%27; by editing 12 genetic variants one’s lifetime risk of bladder cancer could be reduced by almost 75%.28
This application cannot be achieved through current methods of genetic selection. Say a couple want to use PGT to select for 15 different genes in an embryo, to reduce their likelihood of cardiovascular disease. Then they would need to create thou- sands of embryos to make it sufficiently likely that one will have the right combination at all 15 loci. The chance of the couple having such an embryo would be <1% with traditional IVF and PGD.29
Given the massive disease burden caused by chronic diseases, we have strong moral reasons to develop technologies that reduce their incidence—whether these operate through genetic or environmental mechanisms. Imagine scientists develop a new technology which potentially could be incorporated into exhaust filters, and would drastically reduce the amount of air pollution cars emit. In cities where cars are fitted with the exhaust filter, the incidence of respiratory disease would be decreased by 40%.
ii This first require an embryo to be biopsied at very early stage (eg, two-cell or four-cell stage), to reduce risks of mosaicism. iii This possibility was first brought to our attention by Roman Teo Oliynyk’s unpublished manuscript ‘Could future gene therapy prevent aging diseases?’44 iv In each of these case, there is a possibility that people in the low-risk group are overall worse off than those in the high-risk group, as the genes associated with high risk are beneficial in some other way. There will be a need for greater research into the overall effects of particular mutation before this application of HGE was undertaken.
There are clearly strong moral reasons to develop this tech- nology and pursue its applications. Developing the exhaust filter is not merely something it would be permissible to do, but some- thing that there is an imperative to do. The very same reasons apply to the development of HGE.
One might respond that the clear difference between this case and HGE, is that HGE makes heritable changes and will thus affect future generations. However, air pollution is a known epigenetic modifier,30 that is, it makes changes to gene expres- sion which can be inherited by future generations.31 Hence, reducing air pollution could also affect future generations. Of course, we need to consider what the long-term effects of any changes will be. But if the likely effect of a genetic change in one generation is to reduce risk of disease in future generations, this seems only to strengthen the case in favour of those changes.
If HGE could make genetic changes which reduce risks of polygenic disease in current and future generations, there would be an imperative to use it. Obviously, this application is a long way away from being plausible, possibly decades. One major difficulty is that we do not understand polygenic scores well enough to accurately predict the effects of large-scale changes. Still, we have moral reasons to develop HGE with the inten- tion of using them for this purpose. First, it will reduce rates of premature death and disability due to chronic disease. Second, the use of HGE to make the highest risk individuals the same as the lowest risk individuals will be equality-promoting. Third, using HGE to lower the incidence of chronic disease will also promote justice. As stated above, health systems spend billions in resources to treat and prevent chronic disease. Using HGE in germline cells will probably be a relatively cheap way (in the proximity of US$20 000) of reducing someone’s susceptibility to chronic diseases. In a world of limited resources, taking a more expensive therapy has the opportunity cost of preventing the treatment of someone else’s disease. Justice requires we choose the most cost-effective option, other things being equal. If we do not invest in the most cost-effective option, we harm others who could use these resources.
enhancement Just as polygenic scores could in theory be used to reduce rates of complex disease, they can target complex traits like intelligence.
General intelligence—the ability to learn, reason and solve problems—is the best known predictor of education and occu- pational outcomes.32
For decades, it has been known that around 50% of the observed variation in intelligence is due to genetic factors. A number of recent large studies have identified many polymorphisms, which help explain 20% of the heritable variation in intelligence.32
As with complex disease, using the polygenic scores it is possible to stratify the population into three board groups ‘high predisposition to high intelligence’; ‘medium predisposition to high intelligence’ and ‘low predisposition to high intelligence’. It will become theoretically possible to use HGE to shift indi- viduals from the low or medium predisposition groups, into the high predisposition group.
Enhancing based on intelligence using polygenic scores would, in the words of the Nuffield report, be a form of enhancement that uses only ‘wild-type’ variants (variants that already exist in the species) rather than a form of enhancing that goes beyond what currently exists in the species. In other words, it is a form of ‘normal range human enhancement’.33 While it may be possible in the future to enhance intelligence beyond levels that are currently observed in the species—such forms of enhance- ment are much less feasible at present.
521Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
Imagine a prenatal nutritional programme was developed, which was predicted to increase intelligence in children born with low innate predisposition to high intelligence. This would be seen as a breakthrough. We may soon be able to achieve the same with HGE.
One of the most intuitive concerns about technologies like germline engineering is the effect on equality. It is feared that germline engineering would only be available to the rich, and that it could widen the gap between rich and poor, adding biological advantages to already existing social ones. This is an important and complex issue, faced not just by genome editing but other goods like education. Ethically, we must take steps to ensure that the benefits and costs of HGE are evenly or fairly shared. As recognised by the Nuffield Council, this is not a reason to ban the technology, or fail to develop it, but a reason to ensure it is developed responsibly.
However, it is also possible to use HGE to directly improve equality, as the intelligence example shows. Nature is a biolog- ical lottery which has no mind to fairness. Some are born gifted and talented, others with short painful lives or severe disabili- ties. Currently, diet, education, special services and other social interventions are used to correct natural inequality. It may be that targeting combinations of genes is an effective means of promoting equality in education. For example, there are natural variations in people’s innate ability to learn how to read. This often matters little for people in higher socioeconomic groups, who can afford to spend extra time with their children teaching them how to read, or employ tutors, etc. However, for those in lower socioeconomic groups, this predisposition can leave them illiterate for life. While other measures could in theory no doubt remedy this inequity of outcomes, evening out the genetic starting point could prove the most effective way. This method would have the additional benefit of being passed to future generations. Genome editing could be used as a part of public healthcare for egalitarian reasons.
Boosting intelligence and other cognitive traits through HGE will be an ‘enhancement’, rather than disease prevention. As noted by the Nuffield report, this does not by itself reduce the moral reasons we have to pursue it. We have a moral imperative to use all reasonable means to produce equality in education.
Future generations and intergenerational justice One of the key interests considered by the Nuffield Council report is that of future generations. It is crucial that the very long- term consequences of developing or failing to develop HGE be considered. Humans often exhibit a cognitive bias towards the near future and neglect then how our actions may affect the very far future. This can distort our appraisal of technologies.
The obligations we have to future generations are often described in terms of intergenerational justice. We owe future generations the same considerations that we owe our contempo- raries. We should not unnecessarily deplete the ozone layer, for example, if this will greatly harm future persons at an only small benefit to ourselves.
Some worry that by engaging in HGE we risk harming future generations by negatively altering our genome. There is no doubt that some application of HGE could harm future generations (e.g., see discussion of collective action problems in Section 3); however, such applications are not the inevitable consequences of the development of HGE, and can be mitigated or avoided.
Moreover, a deep engagement with the interests of future generations will show why there is strong moral imperative to develop HGE as a matter of intergenerational justice.34
Modern medicine is removing selection pressures that humans have historically been subjected to. This is increasing the rate of random mutations accumulating in the genome and poses a risk to future generations, as made clear by Michael Lynch in a 2016 article in the journal Genetics:
What is exceptional about humans is the recent detachment from the challenges of the natural environment and the ability to modify phenotypic traits in ways that mitigate the fitness effects of mutations, for example, precision and personalized medicine. This results in a relaxation of selection against mildly deleterious mutations, including those magnifying the mutation rate itself. The long-term consequence of such effects is an expected genetic deterioration in the baseline human condition, potentially measurable on the timescale of a few generations in westernized societies.35
As we develop effective and accessible treatments for disease, we all but guarantee that the incidence of those diseases will increase in future generations. This is because mutations which arise that contribute to those diseases are no longer selected against.
For example, short sightedness (myopia) has been historically very rare because it was selected against in hunter-gatherer soci- eties.36 Modern technologies such as glasses, contact lenses and Lasik eye surgery help correct such vision problems. In modern societies, those with naturally poor eyesight have the same fitness as those who have naturally good eyesight. This allows deleterious mutations to occur in the genes which influence vision and not be selected against. Rates of myopia are now over 50% in many countries, making populations increasingly reliant on technology for this basic biological function. It is likely that reduced selection against poor vision has caused some of this increase. While it is easy to correct for myopia, the same process will allow mutations to accumulate in genes which influence other biological functions.
The percentage of people who require blood pressure medi- cation,37 assisted reproductive technologies38 and have genetic predispositions to deafness, are all increasing. While social changes play a major role in these changes (eg, poor diet and sedentary lifestyle, delayed childbearing), biological factors also play an important part.39 40 In future generations, nearly all people may be reliant on technologies for these basic functions, as well as many others.
This will be bad for individuals, who become increasingly dependent on technologies for basic functions, and need to spend much of their time and money acquiring a range of therapeutic goods. Similarly, society will become burdened with spiralling healthcare costs. Furthermore, the consequence of natural disas- ters will become much more severe if people are reliant on a variety of complex technologies whose supply can be disrupted.
Fortunately, there is a way for our descendants to avoid such a medicalised future. Using HGE, we could edit out disease- causing mutations as they arise in our genome. This will allow our descendants to enjoy the same level of genetic health as we enjoy today.
Of course, many diseases have a lifestyle element—we have mentioned cardiovascular disease and infertility. Many resist using biological interventions to treat lifestyle problems. For example, it seems absurd to genetically modify human beings to be able to tolerate a diet consisting solely of foods with low nutritional value.
However, as we have argued, there are biological components to many contemporary diseases that are worthy of modification.
522 Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
Moreover, even if such diseases were entirely lifestyle or social in origin, which intervention we ought to choose—modifying the biological, psychological, social or natural environment— depends on the costs and benefits of the particular interven- tion, and relevant moral values. For example, it may be possible to prevent skin cancer by avoiding exposure to the sun, or by increasing the production of melanin, or by increasing the capacity of our immune cells to attack skin cancers. Which we should choose depends on the context.
A common assumption in environmental ethics is that we have obligations to members of future generations. According to one principle of intergenerational justice, ‘existing generations ought not act so as to worsen the position of future generations by depleting non-renewable resources with no compensatory action or recompense’.41
It is clear that the use of modern medicine is worsening the position of members of future generation, by allowing random mutations to occur to our genome. Fortunately, there is a straight- forward compensatory action—developing HGE. This is not something that is merely permissible—but a moral imperative.
governAnCe And publIC ATTITudes Ultimately, it is up to the public to make decisions about the ways genome editing can be applied. This is a guiding principle of liberal democracies. As noted by the Nuffield Council (p. 162), before any changes are made to the laws governing HGE, broad and inclusive public debate is necessary.
We endorse this view, but wish to add that public debates surrounding HGE need to be supplemented by public educa- tion initiatives. Making truly informed decisions about complex scientific matters requires people to understand science. A recent study by the Pew Study showed that 86% of Americans with high scientific knowledge approved of the use of HGE to prevent diseases that would be apparent at birth. This drops to 56% of people with low knowledge of science.42 Such research shows how familiarity with a subject matter shapes one’s view of it.
The Pew Research also shows a great divide between people who think HGE is permissible to prevent disease (72% for disease present at birth; 60% for later onset diseases) and those that think it is permissible for enhancement (18%). This is inter- esting because as noted by the Nuffield Council, there seems not to be essential reasons as to why the use of HGE to prevent disease is different than its use for human enhancement. What is important is that any use be consistent with promoting indi- vidual welfare, and does not negatively impact society.
Just as is the case with science, for people to make truly informed decision on ethical matters, ethical education is required. People should learn about concepts such as justice, freedom and well-being from an earlier age, and learn how to think critically about such topics. Only then can we truly make informed decisions about technologies like HGE.
ConClusIon Genome editing technologies are developing rapidly, and so too is our understanding of their moral implications. The consensus of various expert bodies on the ethical implications of genome editing has shifted in response to greater engagement with the underlying philosophical issues. This has been exemplified by the recent Nuffield Council report, ‘genome editing and human reproduction’. Rather than drawing arbitrary lines between different possible uses of HGE, the Nuffield Council report engages with the fundamental ethical principles that should
guide our appraisal of genome editing—concerns for individ- uals, for society as a whole and for future generations.
Nonetheless, we think deep engagement with underlying ethical issues of HGE yields much stronger conclusions than those drawn by the Nuffield Council. It will be ‘morally permis- sible’ to engage in HGE and will be morally ‘required’ in some instances.
The human genome was created by a blind process of muta- tion and selection occurring over thousands of generations. This process had no foresight for the creatures it would produce. This has resulted in vast natural inequality. The most extreme examples are single gene disorders, where some people become destined to a short life with much pain due to random quirks in their DNA. Others are born with high risks of chronic disease like heart disease and cancer. We ought to use powerful technol- ogies like HGE to correct these inequalities and promote human flourishing. Such actions are moral imperatives.
Contributors Dr CG conducted the initial research, helped drafted the initial manuscript, made revisions and prepared the manuscript for submission. HBS researched and summarised the Nuffield Council report and other institutional statements, and edited the manuscript. Professor JS conceptualised the project, helped draft the initial manuscript, provided feedback on drafts and made revisions to the manuscript. All authors approved the final manuscript as submitted and agree to be accountable for all aspects of the work.
Funding CG, HBS and JS, through their involvement with the Murdoch, received funding from the Victorian State Government through the Operational Infrastructure Support (OIS) Programme.
Competing interests None declared.
patient consent Not required.
provenance and peer review Commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
data sharing statement Not applicable.
open access This is an open access article distributed in accordance with the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Unported (CC BY 4.0) license, which permits others to copy, redistribute, remix, transform and build upon this work for any purpose, provided the original work is properly cited, a link to the licence is given, and indication of whether changes were made. See: https:// creativecommons. org/ licenses/ by/ 4. 0/.
reFerenCes 1 Jinek M, Chylinski K, Fonfara I, et al. A programmable dual-RNA-guided DNA
endonuclease in adaptive bacterial immunity. Science 2012;337:816–21. 2 Liang P, Xu Y, Zhang X, et al. CRISPR/Cas9-mediated gene editing in human
tripronuclear zygotes. Protein Cell 2015;6:363–72. 3 Ma H, Marti-Gutierrez N, Park SW, et al. Correction of a pathogenic gene mutation in
human embryos. Nature 2017;548:413–9. 4 Practical Ethics. The fundamental ethical flaw in Jiankui he’s alleged gene editing
experiment. 2018 https://www. apnews. com/ 4997 bb7a a36c 4544 9b48 8e19 ac83e86d 5 News AP. Chinese researcher claims first gene-edited babies. 2018 http:// blog.
practicalethics. ox. ac. uk/ 2018/ 11/ the- fundamental- ethical- flaw- in- jiankui- hes- alleged- gene- editing-experiment/
6 Lanphier E, Urnov F, Haecker SE, et al. Don’t edit the human germ line. Nature 2015;519:410–1.
7 The Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Genome editing and human reproduction: social and ethical issues. 2018 http:// nuffieldbioethics. org/ project/ genome- editing- human- reproduction (Accessed 19 Jul 2018).
8 Gyngell C, Douglas T. Stocking the genetic supermarket: reproductive genetic technologies and collective action problems. Bioethics 2015;29:241–50.
9 In: Buchanan AE, Brock DW, eds. rom chance to choice: genetics and justice. 8th printing. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 2007.
10 Singer P. The human genome and the genetic supermarket. Free Inq 2001;21. 11 Power RA, Pluess M. Heritability estimates of the big five personality traits based on
common genetic variants. Transl Psychiatry 2015;5:e604. 12 Diener E, Sandvik E, Pavot W, et al. Extraversion and subjective well-being in a U.S.
national probability sample. J Res Pers 1992;26:205–15. 13 Latham RM, von Stumm S. Mothers want extraversion over conscientiousness or
intelligence for their children. Pers Individ Dif 2017;119:262–5. 14 Jung JH, Lee Y, Karsten R. The moderating effect of extraversion–introversion
differences on group idea generation performance. Small Group Res 2012;43:30–49. 15 Gyngell C, Douglas T. Selecting against disability: the liberal eugenic challenge and
the argument from cognitive diversity. J Appl Philos 2016.
523Gyngell C, et al. J Med Ethics 2019;45:514–523. doi:10.1136/medethics-2018-105084
Feature article
16 Cain S. Quiet: the power of introverts in a world that can’t stop talking. 1st pbk. ed. New York: Broadway Paperbacks, 2013.
17 Bhattacharya K, Wotton T, Wiley V. The evolution of blood-spot newborn screening. Transl Pediatr 2014;3:63–70.
18 Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authorit. Fertility Treatment in 2013. 19 Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. Fertility treatment 2014–2016: trends
and figures. 2018 https://www. hfea. gov. uk/ media/ 2563/ hfea- fertility- trends- and- figures- 2017- v2. pdf.
20 Medical Service Advisory Committee. Assessment of preimplantation genetic diagnosis. 2015.
21 World Health Organisation. Preventing Chronic Diseases a vital investment. http:// www. who. int/ chp/ chronic_ disease_ report/ contents/ part2. pdf (Accessed 31 Aug 2018).
22 Leal J, Luengo-Fernández R, Gray A, et al. Economic burden of cardiovascular diseases in the enlarged European Union. Eur Heart J 2006;27:1610–9.
23 Wheeler E, Barroso I. Genome-wide association studies and type 2 diabetes. Brief Funct Genomics 2011;10:52–60.
24 Peden JF, Farrall M. Thirty-five common variants for coronary artery disease: the fruits of much collaborative labour. Hum Mol Genet 2011;20:R198–205.
25 Chang CQ, Yesupriya A, Rowell JL, et al. A systematic review of cancer GWAS and candidate gene meta-analyses reveals limited overlap but similar effect sizes. Eur J Hum Genet 2014;22:402–8.
26 Chatterjee N, Shi J, García-Closas M. Developing and evaluating polygenic risk prediction models for stratified disease prevention. Nat Rev Genet 2016;17:392–406.
27 Mega JL, Stitziel NO, Smith JG, et al. Genetic risk, coronary heart disease events, and the clinical benefit of statin therapy: an analysis of primary and secondary prevention trials. Lancet 2015;385:2264–71.
28 Garcia-Closas M, Rothman N, Figueroa JD, et al. Common genetic polymorphisms modify the effect of smoking on absolute risk of bladder cancer. Cancer Res 2013;73:2211–20.
29 Bourne H, Douglas T, Savulescu J. Procreative beneficence and in vitro gametogenesis. Monash Bioeth Rev 2012;30:29–48.
30 Maghbooli Z, Hossein-Nezhad A, Ramezani M, et al. Epigenetic alterations and exposure to air pollutants: protocol for a birth cohort study to evaluate the
association between adverse birth outcomes and global DNA methylation. JMIR Res Protoc 2017;6:e29.
31 Bohacek J, Mansuy IM. Epigenetic inheritance of disease and disease risk. Neuropsychopharmacology 2013;38:220–36.
32 Plomin R, von Stumm S, von SS. The new genetics of intelligence. Nat Rev Genet 2018;19:148–59.
33 Kahane G, Savulescu J. Normal human variation: refocussing the enhancement debate. Bioethics 2015;29:133–43.
34 Powell R. In genes we trust: germline engineering, eugenics, and the future of the human genome. J Med Philos 2015;40:jhv025.
35 Lynch M. Mutation and human exceptionalism: our future genetic load. Genetics 2016;202:869–75.
36 Cordain L, Eaton SB, Brand Miller J, et al. An evolutionary analysis of the aetiology and pathogenesis of juvenile-onset myopia. Acta Ophthalmol Scand 2002;80:125–35.
37 Gu Q, Burt VL, Dillon CF, et al. Trends in antihypertensive medication use and blood pressure control among United States adults with hypertension: the National Health And Nutrition Examination Survey, 2001 to 2010. Circulation 2012;126:2105–14.
38 Adamson GD, Tabangin M, Macaluso M, et al. The number of babies born globally after treatment with the assisted reproductive technologies (ART). Fertil Steril 2013;100:S42.
39 Hanevik HI, Hessen DO, Sunde A, et al. Can IVF influence human evolution? Hum Reprod 2016;31:1397–402.
40 Nance WE, Kearsey MJ. Relevance of connexin deafness (DFNB1) to human evolution. Am J Hum Genet 2004;74:1081–7.
41 Page E. Intergenerational Justice and Climate Change. Polit Stud 1999;47:53–66. 42 Funk C, Hefferon M. Public Views of Gene Editing for Babies Depend on How It Would
Be Used. Pew Res Cent Internet Sci Tech 2018 http://www. pewinternet. org/ 2018/ 07/ 26/ public- views- of- gene- editing- for- babies- depend- on- how- it- would- be- used/ (Accessed 30 Aug 2018).
43 Gyngell C, Douglas T, Savulescu J. The ethics of germline gene editing. J Appl Philos 2017;34.
44 Oliynyk RT. Quantifying the potential for future gene therapy to lower lifetime risk of polygenic late-onset diseases. bioRxiv 2018.
- Moral reasons to edit the human genome: picking up from the Nuffield report
- Abstract
- Introduction
- The Nuffield Council’s report on genome editing and human reproduction
- Principle 1: the welfare of the future person
- Principle 2: social justice and solidarity
- Social harms and collective action problems
- Modified principle 2: social harms
- Categorical limits and moral imperatives in HGE
- Single gene disorders
- Preimplantation genetic testing and HGE
- Polygenic diseases
- Enhancement
- Future generations and intergenerational justice
- Single gene disorders
- Governance and public attitudes
- Conclusion
- References